A (way) while back Charli posted a link to a report by Landmine Action. The short version is that it is calling for a ban on so-called ‘blast-weapons’ as a method of warfare.
From the outset I’m going to admit that it’s simply not easy to defend things that can blow innocent civilians to smithereens. And I don’t intent to defend the weapons themselves as some kind of fabulous invention. I do, however, wish to take on some of the thinking and insertions in the report as I think that 1) the report is problematic; 2) that there may actually be a case for not banning such weapons – possibly even humanitarian ones. Instead, states AND humanitarians should look to regulation as a more effective alternative.
My response ended up being longer than what I thought so I’m going to attempt to do this over the course of a few posts. I feel that this is important because next year (2011) marks the next round of discussions on the Convention on Conventional Weapons where it is likely that proposals to ban such weapons will be discussed. At recent CCW meetings the inability of ‘militarily significant states’ and restriction-inclined states to agree on bans of certain categories of weapons have lead to separate treaty regimes – famously the 1997 Ottawa Landmines Treaty and the Cluster Munitions Treaty. While the CCW does not get a lot of love or recognition, it will be important for government lawyers and humanitarians to think through these issues now.
In the executive summary of the report it is argued that:
Explosive weapons have a high capacity to damage the social and economic infrastructure on which civilian populations rely. The destruction of housing, power supplies, water and sanitation systems, health facilities, schools, markets, roads and transport links, and energy infrastructure present direct humanitarian problems, deplete local and national capacity for production and growth, and necessitate high levels of reconstruction expenditure, diverting scarce resources from investments necessary to achieving developmental targets
Basically – when bombs land, stuff gets blown up. Sometimes it’s hard to rebuild. This is a major thrust of the report – but it’s hardly rocket science. Blowing something up in war has (or should have) that very purpose – to deplete the capacity of the enemy to resist your will. In doing so, a state is likely to target those things which give the enemy the capacity to resist – which may mean blowing things up which may be hard to rebuild.
So while I don’t object to anything specifically in the above paragraph, I think it is somewhat missing the point. Such actions are usually legal. This doesn’t, of course, make them nice or particularly friendly to populations which will have to rebuild. However, so long as such actions are proportional and militarily necessary, no violation of the law of war is committed.
But there are some very strange passages in the report in which I do strongly disagree. For example:
At the same time, the use of explosive violence by non-state actors is increasing. This report notes that trend and argues that the state-asserted monopoly on explosive weapons is not being maintained in practice. Furthermore the unacceptability of non-state use of explosive weapons is diminished by the failure of states to enact appropriate categorical controls on the use of these weapons in populated areas, or to attend to the relationships of diminished local accountability that such use articulates.
The argument here is that non-state use is effectively legitimized by state use of weapons. To back up this statement, the Report only cites the man who endorses the report in the introduction. (FYI: That’s John Holmes, Under-Secretary-General for Humanitarian Affairs and Emergency Relief Coordinator.)
From an international legal standpoint this argument is flatly and categorically wrong. First, there is the rather obvious point that the legitimacy of your actions depends on who you are as much as what you do in warfare. International law has always made a distinction between state and non-state actors – the former (at least in theory) subject to accountability proceedings, military codes of conduct and, if it all goes wrong, potentially severe penalties. The latter has no means for following/implementing the laws of war, nor any mechanisms for training or enforcement within their ranks. And this is a huge difference that the Executive Summary ignores. The report is effectively comparing an indiscriminate suicide bomb carried out in a market to a weapon used, albeit harshly, that was nevertheless likely subject to legal advice and due diligence.
Secondly, this quote seems to somehow be suggesting that one wrong rights another. It’s clear that the author is speaking on a moral level here – but this is again very much untrue in the laws of war and its a misleading statement at best.
There are other similar and even more globalzationish statements throughout the executive summary. For example, globalisation means that we have to now change the way we think we use weapons (without ever explaining exactly why this is):
A context of globalisation and increased transnational interdependence between peoples and states argues for stronger requirements of local accountability for potential users of explosive weapons, and for increasing the burden of justification, and threshold of acceptability, for explosive weapon use;
Why, exactly? Because more people are watching? Because we can now chat on the internet? Because I can “like” the rebel group that I support on Facebook? There has always been transnational links when it comes to weapons, soldiers mercenaries, etc. This is hardly a new thing and not exactly a powerful argument.
Another paragraph in the executive summary also caught my eye:
There is no doubt that weapon technologies developed over the last 200 years have exponentially increased the capacity of humankind to kill and injure itself. Whilst technology cannot be ‘un-thought’, the same period has also provided some grounds for optimism that identified categories of weapon technology can be rendered less acceptable, and hence less likely to be used, by changes in the social and economic context.
Yes – the invention of chemical, biological and nuclear weapons (not to mention MOABs, napalm, etc) have created the potential for many deaths and significant levels of destruction. However, technology has also rendered precision guidance systems that could not have been imagined even thirty years ago. Whereas in the First Gulf war only 10% of munitions were precision guided, 90% of bombs in the Second Gulf war were PGMs.
By no means does this allow for or guarantee a “clean” war – such as what the Landmine Action advocates seem to be seeking. But to suggest that the progress of weaponry has been in an entirely anti-humanitarian manner is incorrect.
I think this may reflect an overall problem with the kind of thinking in the report – namely that it overlooks (or at least fails to acknowledge) that there are obligations on defenders as well as attackers. Defenders have an obligation to conduct their hostilities away from certain objects – centres of religious worship, hospitals, schools, etc. Their presence legitimately renders an immune target vulnerable. Of course, this is what they want – to cause attackers to hit things which essentially “look bad” and to cause international outrage.
After all, this is what has been at the heart of so much criticism of US bombing campaigns in recent years. (Although this cannot excuse casualties in cases of negligence.)
There are also several related issues to this point that one could highlight. First, “dual use” targets – those things which have both a civilian and military use such as a water tower, railways, some factories, etc. In his account of the war in Kosovo, General Wesley Clark made it clear that this was a major hurdle for the allies to get over. Europeans tend to take a much narrower view as to what constitutes a military target when something may be used for both civilian and military purposes while Americans take a much broader approach.
Second, just how much damage may be done? It usually comes down to the inexact science of ‘proportionality’ of which there are two components. First, there is the proportionality in the jus ad bellum criteria. Is our response proportionate to the overall threat? Second, the proportionality of a specific attack to the necessity of what you are trying to accomplish in a particular strike. There is, quite simply, no objective criterion for making a determination on either front. We might be able to recognize a violation of the principle when it occurs (a daisy cutter in response to a dump truck with an AK-47 would be a slightly absurd example) but even then it would probably have to be argued about in the court of international (and quite possibly domestic) opinion.The report seems to be suggesting that long-term damage is disproportionate, but without any context upon which we can measure proportionality, I would argue that from a legal standpoint this is impossible to know and judge without context.
I’m going to leave it here for now, but will shortly be returning to issues of ‘stigmatizing’ weapons and banning on the basis of intent or effects. Thereafter a post on the problems with weapons bans and the approach taken by some humanitarian organizations.
“the legitimacy of your actions depends on who you are as much as what you do in warfare. International law has always made a distinction between state and non-state actors – the former (at least in theory) subject to accountability proceedings, military codes of conduct and, if it all goes wrong, potentially severe penalties. ” – Indeed, but not the way you seem to think. Who you are (winner vs. loser) has a huge effect on what kinds of legal claims will be available afterwards and by what standards those claims will be judged. The victors and their friends are generally the ones to establish tribunals/courts, and they usually get to determine what the terms of legal reference for arbitration will be. There is no higher power than power.
@Ben, I'm sorry but that doesn't really make any sense. If that was the case, then why is it that the vast majority of criticism is directed at western forces in Afghanistan? I mean, is it just that we expect it from the Taliban? I'd say that power, from a humanitarian stance, always attracts criticism.(As it probably should… And power should be able to justify its actions.) But this is just politically speaking. Legally there is no basis for what you're saying. If it was just 'victors justice' then there would be no basis for the laws of war at all.
A couple of points.
First, you do not seem to distinguish between the legality of an action, and its legitimacy. There are actions that may be illegal, but appear (to certain participants and observers at least) to be perfectly legitimate, even morally right. Conversely, there are actions that can be taken that are legal, but nonetheless appear to be immoral and therefore illegitimate. Referring to only the legality of an action tends to obscure the fact that some people care less about what is in accordance with international law than others do — and may even have what they consider to be morally convincing — as opposed to narrowly self-interested (as in the case of bank robbers) reasons to believe so.
Second, the argument that interdependence requires stronger measures of local accountability is based upon a conception of cosmopolitan ethics — we owe a duty of care to all of humanity now, not just to our own fellow-citizens, because we (as in humans) are in a real sense much more closely connected — economically, culturally, socially — than we previously were. We have empathic points of entry into the suffering of others that we did not have 50 or 100 years ago; accordingly it is more difficult to ignore the consequences of our governments' actions.
The bottom line is that, just because what you did is legal, it does not necessarily follow that it was just, or right.
.
In the executive summary of the report it is argued that:
“Explosive weapons have a high capacity to damage the social and economic infrastructure on which civilian populations rely. The destruction of housing, power supplies, water and sanitation systems, health facilities, schools, markets, roads and transport links, and energy infrastructure present direct humanitarian problems, deplete local and national capacity for production and growth, and necessitate high levels of reconstruction expenditure, diverting scarce resources from investments necessary to achieving developmental targets”
It is a real long time since I was current on gunnery, but as I remember a kinetic energy round (a piece of steel) would normally do more damage to infrastructure than the same sized exposive explosive round hitting the same target. That was in the bad old days before steel was upgraded to deleted uranium.
I think the people who are making the proposal need to do some more research. Their proposal is to simplistic to reliably accomplish their goal.
I clearly can’t agree with many of your points made above, but here just a few comments that come to my mind:
The report is “missing the point. Such actions are usually legal.” – Obviously, the report goes beyond narrow legal questions. More fundamentally, it challenges what we consider “acceptable” or “normal” practices of warfare today on the basis of evidence that the use of explosive weapons in the close vicinity of civilians causes a distinct pattern of civilian harm.
“so long as such actions are proportional and militarily necessary, no violation of the law of war is committed” – this statement is not accurate in legal terms. But more importantly, even if proportionality was respected, just because civilian harm is not “excessive” does not mean it is not “extensive”. Extensive civilian harm constitutes a serious humanitarian problem that needs to be addressed.
And if one wanted to think about this subject solely in terms of the law, what about distinction? The blast and fragmentation effects of explosive weapons radiate outward from a point of detonation and affect a zone within which no distinction is possible. Depending on the size of that zone and its location – e.g. a market, bus stand, residential area – can we really claim the principle of distinction can be respected?
And finally about claims, can a user really claim to implement IHL as required, or that an attack was proportionate, or that all necessary precautions had been taken, if the user does not systematically collect relevant data on the impacts of attacks? I think not.
Maybe Landmine Action will be happier when we institute regional disintegration chambers, where the civilian “victims” of computer-simulated warfare will have to report upon finding out that their area was hit by simulated munitions. Then war will be all clean and efficient, without destroying any infrastructure.
Cute, but out of context. On Eminiar VII, it is civilians who are being marched into the disintegration chamber to avoid damage to societal infrastructure. What is being proposed here in real life is the opposite – to minimize civilian casualties – and arguments about protecting infrastructure are a means to that end, not an end in itself. More here.
I agree completely.