Debating the Benefits of Nuclear Superiority for Crisis Bargaining, Part II

25 March 2013, 1305 EDT

Editor’s Note: Back in February I riffed on a post by Erik Voeten in which Erik discussed two articles in International Organization (IO). One, by our colleague Matt Kroenig, argued that nuclear superiority gives states advantages in crisis bargaining (PDF). Another, by Todd Sechser and Matthew Fuhrmann, rejects this claim (PDF).

After the two posts sparked some interesting discussion–both on- and offline–I approached all three about doing a mini-symposium at the Duck of Minerva. They agreed.  Earlier we ran Kroenig’s piece. In this post, Sechser and Fuhrmann critique the claims he made in his IO article. Both sides will have an opportunity to respond.

Iran’s nuclear program has been a source of international concern for a long time. Some observers in Israel and the United States are now pushing for war, arguing that a nuclear Iran would brandish its capability like a club, waving it around recklessly and bullying neighbors and rivals into submission with nuclear threats.

This fear stems from a common belief that nuclear weapons are more than just weapons of self-defense and deterrence – they are offensive diplomatic tools as well.  But is this view correct?  Are nuclear weapons useful for coercion and intimidation?

Nuclear weapons have little impact on the effectiveness of coercive threats.

We recently conducted a study that found a surprising answer.  Our study, published in the journal International Organization, investigated whether nuclear states enjoy more coercive success than other states. We found that they do not: nuclear weapons have little impact on the effectiveness of coercive threats.  (Note that we use the term “coercive” to refer to attempts to persuade an adversary to change its behavior or give up something valuable.  This is distinct from deterrence, where the goal is to preserve the status quo, not change it.)

Our conclusion challenges conventional thinking about nuclear weapons, which holds that nuclear weapons are useful for coercion – and not just deterrence – simply because they are so destructive.  This view argues that nuclear-armed states can more easily compel others to make concessions in international crises – and that they can do so without actually going to war.  But the conventional view fails to fully appreciate two important limitations of nuclear weapons.

First, nuclear weapons are not very good for seizing disputed objects, like territory. It would make little sense, for example, for Pakistan to try to take Kashmir by launching an offensive nuclear attack against Indian forces there. Doing so would kill ethno-religious kin and could render portions of the land uninhabitable.

Instead, Pakistan would be more likely to say (or insinuate) something like “Give us Kashmir or we will attack New Delhi.” But this brings us to a second point: carrying out a coercive nuclear threat would be tremendously costly. A state that launched a nuclear attack to achieve a coercive objective – that is, to obtain something it didn’t have already – would provoke an enormous international backlash.  The consequences could include economic sanctions, diplomatic isolation, efforts by neighbors to acquire their own nuclear weapons, and even military interventions against the coercer.

Of course, the costs of enacting a threat are only one part of the equation, and these costs might be worth paying if one’s survival were at risk. But states making coercive threats rarely face such dire circumstances. Indeed, a key feature of coercion is that the coercer is seeking something that it has already been living without – such as a piece of disputed territory, monetary reparations, or reversal of an unfavorable policy.  While these stakes are hardly trivial, in most cases they are not so vital to the coercer’s security as to outweigh the inevitable backlash that would follow an offensive nuclear strike.  Pakistan would desperately like to acquire Kashmir, but having lived without it for decades, Pakistan’s survival hardly depends on possessing it.  The very nature of coercion thus works against the credibility of nuclear coercive threats.

Nuclear powers should be no more successful, on average, when trying to coerce their adversaries.

A simple prediction follows from our argument: nuclear powers should be no more successful, on average, when trying to coerce their adversaries. Our study tested this proposition by examining compellent threats in international crises.  (A compellent threat, as originally conceived by Thomas Schelling, is a coercive demand designed to compel an adversary to change the status quo.) Specifically, we set out to determine whether nuclear states make more effective compellent threats than nonnuclear states.

After looking at more than 200 compellent threats, we found that nuclear states issue successful threats just 20 percent of the time, while nonnuclear coercers succeed more than 30 percent of the time.  These results also hold when we apply more advanced statistical techniques and control for confounding variables.  This is not the pattern we would see if nuclear weapons are useful tools of coercion.

The recent experience of the United States bears this logic out well.  Consider how many American coercive threats have failed in the last quarter-century: Panama (1989), Iraq (1990-91 and 2003), Afghanistan (1998 and 2001), and Serbia (1999), for starters.  One might also include implicit threats against North Korea and Iran on this list.  By contrast, U.S. coercive successes during this period are few and far between, including just Haiti (1994) and Iraq (temporarily, in 1997).  In all of these cases, the United States possessed a diverse nuclear arsenal and nuclear superiority over its opponent.  Yet most of these threats were unsuccessful.

A recent article by Matthew Kroenig, in the same issue of International Organization, appears to challenge our findings. Kroenig argues that nuclear weapons do convey advantages in crisis bargaining, but only when a state has nuclear superiority – that is, when it has more nuclear weapons than its opponent.  After analyzing 20 crises, he reports “a powerful relationship between nuclear superiority and victory in nuclear crises” (p. 143).  Our study of 200 threats, by contrast, found no such relationship.

A closer look at Kroenig’s evidence, however, reveals that it is actually quite supportive of our argument. First, according to the International Crisis Behavior project, the nuclear-superior side actually “won” just 10 of the 20 crises that Kroenig evaluates, losing or settling for a stalemate in the other 10.  (See the table below.)  In other words, the effect of nuclear superiority basically amounts to a coin flip: on average, the side with nuclear superiority fares about as well as the side without it.

Crisis

Start Year

Winning Side

Victory for Nuclear Superiority?

Korean War

1950

None

No

Suez crisis

1956

United States, Soviet Union

Yes

Berlin deadline

1958

None

No

Berlin Wall

1961

Soviet Union

No

Cuban missile crisis

1962

United States

Yes

Congo crisis

1964

United States

Yes

Six-Day War

1967

United States, Israel

Yes

Sino-Soviet border war

1969

None

No*

War of attrition

1970

None

No

Cienfuegos submarine base

1970

United States

Yes

Yom Kippur War

1973

United States

Yes

War in Angola

1975

Soviet Union

No

Afghanistan invasion

1979

Soviet Union

Yes

Able Archer exercise

1983

None

No

Nicaragua, MIG-21s

1984

None

No

Kashmir

1990

None

No

Taiwan Strait crisis

1995

United States

Yes

India/Pakistan nuclear tests

1998

None

No

Kargil crisis

1999

India

Yes

Indian Parliament attack

2001

India

Yes

*Kroenig recodes this case to be a Soviet victory and therefore a victory for nuclear superiority, but the creators of this dataset coded the outcome as a stalemate, not a Soviet victory.

Second, many of the “victories” for nuclear-superior states in Kroenig’s data are successes for deterrence, not coercion.  For example, Kroenig counts the 1995-96 Taiwan Strait crisis as a “victory” for the United States over China.  During this crisis, China conducted military exercises in the East China Sea and issued hostile statements towards the government in Taipei, mainly to prevent pro-independence moves by the Taiwanese government. To protect Taiwan, the United States deployed an aircraft carrier and other ships to the Strait. Kroenig counts this as a U.S. victory, presumably because China did not attack Taiwan.  But even if American nuclear superiority contributed to this outcome – which we doubt – the effect of the U.S. nuclear arsenal was to deter, not coerce.

Overall, Kroenig’s study provides little reason to doubt our conclusion that nuclear (and nuclear-superior) states have no particular advantage in coercive bargaining.

All of this implies that fears about Iranian nuclear blackmail are at least somewhat overblown.  A nuclear Iran might indeed attempt to use its nuclear arsenal for coercive purposes, but history suggests that it is unlikely to succeed.  Coercive nuclear threats have rarely worked in the past, and we see no reason to expect that pattern to change in the future.