Tag: Weber

Slow boring…

Shorter LGM response(s) to Connor Freidersdorf: “Weber.”

Of course, that doesn’t resolve the debate. It merely puts it on the correct footing. 

Share

Legitimate Rape: A Weberian Analysis

On Facebook, someone familiar to readers of this blog wrote: “As readers of Weber know, there are three forms of legitimate rape: forcible, fraternity, and rational-legal.” But enough of that neo-Weberian claptrap. As a good paleo-Weberian knows, the ideal types here remain traditional, charismatic, and legal-rational. And these help us to understand the political backlash over Rep. Aiken’s Aken’s “unfortunate” choice of words.

Aken subscribes to a traditional view of rape. Indeed, his understanding harkens back to late medieval Europe. That’s pretty traditional.

His opponents, on the other hand, adopt legal-rational conceptions of rape. These depend on entirely different warrants, such as consistency, equal application, and other justificatory schema alien to Aken’s wing of the Republican party. Or, as Bryan Fischer of the American Family Association nicely summarized, “What Akin meant by ‘legitimate rape:’ actual forcible rape, not consensual sex that later gets called rape. Come on, people.”

Indeed, since women cannot, for people such as Aken and Fischer, become pregnant from rape, pregnancy provides an excellent basis for distinguishing between traditional rape and faux rape — the latter including mere threats to inflict harm, the exploitation of power differentials, and the droit de segnieur that our great democracy has extended to all men encountering women with short skirts, low-cut tops, or lesbian tendencies.

Ah, traditional justice. So much easier and more accurate than that demanded in legal-rational systems.


Where was I?…. Ah, yes. The problem for Aken is that he failed to translate traditional understandings of legitimate rape into legal-rational ones of the kind demanded by the lamestream media. Many Republicans, however, depend upon making appeals to segments of the electorate whose traditions are more thoroughly laced with legal-rational lifeworlds. They have therefore thrown Aken under the proverbial chariot. But not to worry, for as Weber teaches us a Charismatic figure may create a genuine rupture in existing modes of legitimate rape and build a new order.

And that figure is at hand.

No. Wait. 
Wrong picture.

Sorry. I meant this one:

Credit: TMZ via Salon

I admit none of this was terribly funny. But there’s a serious point here: Weber’s ideal-typical accounts of legitimate domination provide a useful way of parsing contemporary debates in the United States. It isn’t just a matter of content, nor of communities of discourse, but of styles of legitimation.

Share

The Monopoly

Why should academics and policymakers prioritize a state’s acquistion of  “… the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force within a given territory”? Obviously, this monopoly is fundamental to masking the violence of the state in daily domestic affairs, but what about in areas where that violence cannot be masked under the guise of a neutral, rational-legal state that speaks for the “nation” in the first place? Is a Eurocentric model of the state still an appropriate priority for all territories, particularly in regions which have a long history of embattled states as well as fractured societies, and which are experiencing multi-pronged challenges to state authority?

Historically, of course, “pre-modern” states did not always feel the need or desire to acquire a monopoly on the legitimate use of violence. For example, one of the greatest imperial states in history, the Mughal Empire which eventually covered much of modern South Asia (including Afghanistan), never sought or obtained a monopoly on violence and this “failure” did not hinder its progress. At the height of its power in the 17th century, the Mughal empire was more opulent than all of Europe combined. The cultural and particularly the architectural achievements of this imperial state are still considered among the finest in the world. Technologically, in 1526 it was the first to introduce the combined use of handguns and cannons with its military in the sub-continent. While its military superiority would eventually decline, it was never more than a decade behind its rivals in terms of military technology. In any case, in the early and middle period of the empire, the Mughal army could defeat any single opponent on the open battlefield, including European upstarts (see Child’s War 1686-1690). Economically, the empire produced goods for the world market. The arrival of European merchants only further extended direct trade links to northern and western Europe, although prior to industrialization there was little to nothing that the Europeans could offer in exchange for goods produced in South Asia except silver bullion.

The Mughal state had some of the trappings of a modern state, including a large bureaucracy and an extensive police and intelligence apparatus. However, it did not seek to disarm the peasantry or dispossess local and regional rivals who acknowledged its superiority. In fact, as Peter Lorge argues in The Asian Military Revolution (Cambridge, 2008, pp. 130-131), Mughal emperors sat atop a vast “military labor market” of over 4 million infantrymen. The Mughal state’s confidence rested on the fact that it had the best concentration of infantry and equipment as well as a massive treasury and spy network. The goal of the emperor was not to disarm its local and regional rivals, but to manage violence. In other words, the objective was “… to maintain the internal balance of center and periphery, not to annihilate external threats to the throne,” (Lorge 2008, p. 138). This balance was maintained in part by keeping the state literally on the move  en masse from one hot spot to the next. The treasury could also be used to purchase a sufficient additional supply of soldier in order to deny those resources to regional rivals. In any case, military resistance to this peripatetic imperial state by regional rivals was often part of an elaborate bargaining procedure for improving one’s rank within the finely graded official status hierarchy. Of course, once it was weakened by fighting against the guerrilla tactics of the Maratha Confederacy in the mid-17th century, the empire began a steady decline, eventually succumbing to domination by their British vassals and the creation of a “modern state” which did vigorously pursue a strategy to disarm the countryside and to monopolize legitimate violence. Notably, however, the emperor remained remarkably legitimate to large numbers of Hindus and Muslims even up to the dying days of the empire as the Great Rebellion of 1857 demonstrated.

I ask the question about the need for a monopoly not because I want to bring Babur & Co. back from the dead (although… well… that would be fun… after all, nobody parties quite like a Timurid…) but because it is clear that there are several territories in contemporary international affairs where the claim to a monopoly on legitimate use of violence is clearly unlikely to be established in the near future. Labeling such states as “failed” or “failing” in lazy and counter productive.

In places like Afghanistan, for example, the state does not have the monopoly of the legitimate use of force and won’t for the foreseeable future; Afghans know they will have to pay homage indefinitely to a range of actors who have the ability to threaten the use of violence against them: warlords, insurgents, foreign troops, the police, etc. As Noah Coburn argues in Bazaar Politics: Power and Pottery in an Afghan Market Town (Stanford 2011, pp. 182-207), the Afghan state cannot serve as a vertical container of societal conflicts because many of the major actors in society are rivals of the state. Coburn adds that even the notion of a discrete border between the state and society is an artificial construct maintained in large part by society to prop up the state. In other words, the Afghan state is so weak and porous that it is up to society to sustain the illusion of the state as rational and professional. Maintaining the illusion allows aid to flow and keeps the peace, such as it is. Nonetheless, the population is not motivated solely by fear of violence, Afghans value the idea of a sovereign state and the integrity of their state’s territory. The people of Afghanistan do not want their country partitioned or to have their state’s sovereignty further diminished or humiliated by regional or global actors. At the same time, people are realistic enough to know that the state will not vanquish the insurgents and warlords — even with massive international military and financial assistance.

But the choice is not between a monopoly on violence or total anarchy. For embattled states the issue is whether the effort to prioritize acquiring a monopoly by defeating the insurgency and all other challengers to the state is realistic. Building up massive armies in weak states through foreign funding is unsustainable if the state is ever to regain full sovereignty. Moreover, the prolonged presence of foreign troops and unaccountable international non-governmental organizations often undermines the state’s authority and autonomy as much as warlords and insurgents. Perhaps the aim should be to develop sufficient violence capability and financial patronage to keep rival coercive threats in check. To paraphrase Coburn’s depiction of the Afghan state a few years ago: it is too weak to be despotic but strong enough to keep warlords from the temptation of increasing their despotism. Perhaps that should be considered both sufficient and realistic as a marker of success, no? If so, then the question becomes how many elite forces, how much hi-tech weaponry, and how much direct budgetary support would be necessary to maintain that balance while gradually strengthening the state’s ability to increase revenue extraction. This advice will be lost on the US and its partners who are moving toward the exit doors, but India, Russia, and Iran may see its wisdom after 2014…

Share

Scholars and Politics

Stuart and my article — which I blogged about a few days ago — has generated a decent amount of discussion over at Crooked Timber, as well as some here at the Duck. A few people have also e-mailed me privately too. All of this has sparked some further reflection on my part — which I present below the fold for your reading pleasure.

I’ll take up three points: Henry Farrell’s suggestion that we need political action to make space for Weberian-objective scholarship in the public realm; the question of whether any intervention into a public debate is necessarily political and should be evaluated according to those standards; and the question of the role that scholars have or should have when dealing with the broader public.

1) Henry Farrell writes that “political activity is necessary to secure the space for actual academic debate (let alone to have this debate resonate more widely) and that the alternative strategy of pure Weberian activism is doomed to irrelevance” because in present-day America, academics don’t have the kind of social authority that they did in early-20th century Germany — which means that scholarly interventions are going to be perceived as partisan. I agree with Henry that the social capital commanded by the professorate in present-day America is certainly an order of magnitude weaker than that commanded by traditional German academic brahmins; among other things, this speaks to and reflects the rather pervasive anti-intellectualism of American society, which has a long and not-so-disinguished history marvelously chronicled by people like Richard Hofstadter and Thomas Frank.

So yes, scholars start from a disadvantage in the contemporary United States. But I don’t think that this means that we need political action to address this disadvantage. For one thing, I’m not sure that this is a political problem so much as a cultural problem — the absence of a socially meaningful space from which to speak as scholars, and the absence of the kind of cultural resources that could even in principle justify or sustain such a space. It probably is a good idea to work on the development or rehabilitation of cultural resources that would legitimate intellectual activity and the scholarly life, but this is a long-term project that involves a sustained engagement with the long American tradition of anti-intellectualism.

Also, Henry specifically recommends that “academics to get out there, and to deliberately, specifically, and politically attack the people who are seeking to undermine the very concept of academic inquiry.” But what precisely is political about this? Pointing out that a claim is not, in fact, scholarly or scientific is a perfectly appropriate activity for scholars or scientists to engage in. Doing so requires the scholars in question to have a relatively precise delimitation of what constitutes scholarship. I’d suggest that the easiest way to make a case like this is to be able to point to one’s own practice as an example — which is difficult to do if any attempt to distinguish between politics and scholarship is taken to be a “political” act!

Let me use Weber’s notion of ideal-typification to make this point more clearly. Weber argues that social-scientific knowledge — indeed, knowledge in general — is ideal-typical rather than either classically objective (which would be a pure representation of mind-independent, externally existing objects) or purely subjective (which would be a pure expression of an individual’s idiosyncratic observations and values). An ideal-type mediates between these two alternatives, since ideal-typical knowledge starts off with value-commitments but proceeds to refine those value-commitments into conceptual instruments that can be used to make sense out of empirical situations. Weber calls this “objectivity,” but since it’s such a different use of the term than the classical definition, it’s probably better to call it “Weberian objectivity.”

Weber’s types of authority (rational-legal, traditional, and charismatic) are ideal-typical in this sense: starting with a set of values about the relationships between governments and people, Weber fashions three conceptual categories that can then be applied to actually existing polities as a way of explaining and understanding their dynamics. And this means that any knowledge generated through this application is neither classically objective nor purely subjective, but ideal-typical.

Given this, we can broadly differentiate between three kinds of empirical critique of knowledge-claims and those making them:

a) your value-commitments are wrong.
b) your conceptual instruments don’t accurately reflect your values.
c) your application of your conceptual instruments is flawed.

Critiques b) and c) are appropriate scholarly criticisms, because they deal with the way in which knowledge-claims are produced and speak directly to the epistemological status of the claims. Critique a) is not an appropriate scholarly criticism, because it focuses the exchange on value-questions that are most likely intractable (unless we want to make heroic assumptions about the ultimate commensurability of value-claims . . . which opens a whole can of worms that should be labeled “the Enlightenment project,” and that’s a long discussion for another time). “I disagree with your values” (critique a) is more of a ethical/political claim; “I don’t think that you did that correctly” (critiques b and c) is a scholarly claim.

To bring this back to Henry: taking on the claim of a pundit and showing how it is methodologically problematic, or showing how it is nothing more than the expression of a value and therefore not a scholarly claim at all, is not a political attack. It is a perfectly appropriate scholarly activity. So contra Henry, I do not think that we need politics to establish the conditions under which scholarly claims can be taken seriously; I think we scholars need to be more assertive about demarcating punditry from scholarship. Not all empirical claims are created equal, and there’s nothing political about pointing that out.

2) did SSSFP fail? I have to admit that I probably should have pressed harder for the article Stuart and I wrote to have a question-mark in the title, because I’m not entirely sure that the effort did fail. From a political point of view, yes, we failed, inasmuch as policy was not altered. But that’s an appropriate standard for politics, not necessarily for scholarship. Personally, I think that we in SSSFP would have failed if we had taken in more explicitly partisan money and run full-page newspaper ads in swing states, because we would have abandoned any hint of scholarly (Weberian) objectivity.

I think that one of the temptations with a scholarly intervention like the SSSFP campaign is to start thinking of it as a piece of political activity. If we do that, then yes, SSSFP failed — but it was also inept and naive, so its failure was probably overdetermined (and Andreas is probably right that getting an appearance on The Daily Show might have been the best avenue to pursue, since criticism has become satire and vice versa). But if we think of it as something else, then the SSSFP campaign did its job: it pointed out flaws and failures in the then-current Iraq policy. Maybe we could have communicated that somewhat more effectively, but I don’t think the effort was a clear-cut “failure.”

3) all of this leads up to a more basic question: what exactly is the role of scholars with respect to public debates? How should scholars think about their responsibilities when a public discussion enters an area where they have a certain level of professional competence? As should be clear by now, I don’t think that scholars ought to be using the standards appropriate to politicians when trying to think these things through. But I’m also not of the opinion that scholars ought to say and do nothing publicly; if I thought that I wouldn’t very well be blogging about anything related to world politics, and obviously I wouldn’t have been involved in SSSFP. And I will admit that when I first heard about the nascent campaign, I was somewhat skeptical that the planned public intervention could be made without the compromise of scholarly integrity — something I am rather acutely sensitive to since I teach at a university here in Coruscant, where the boundary between scholarly and political activity is sometimes, shall we say, “blurry” — because my basic strategy for several years before that point had been to simply refrain from even commenting on current political issues as much as possible. But obviously I eventually thought that SSSFP was okay, so how and on what basis did I come to that position?

In the end, the key issue for me — and I offer this not as a prescription for everyone, but as a contribution to an ongoing process of thinking these things through — was my sense that scholars, and academics in particular, are social surplus. I mean two things by that: first, that scholarship is not something that is necessary to the functioning and the survival of human society; and second, that scholarship and academia are the kind of thing that wealthy societies can afford precisely because they are wealthy, which means that they are generating resources beyond those resources that have to be consumed in order for the society to survive. (My thinking on this is rather decisively influenced by the French poststructuralist George Bataille, who argues — among other things — that we ought to be analyzing societies and economic systems based on how they spend their surpluses, rather than on how they manage scarce resources.) To be a scholar, to be an academic, is in this sense a very great privilege: somehow, social resources are so configured as to make it possible for us to get paid for reading, writing, and thinking about things — and facilitating student encounters with those things. How “surplus” is that?

So thinking about it in this way changes the question somewhat. Since scholars are social surplus, what do we owe the society that makes us possible? I would say that what scholars owe in the first instance is that they be scholars, which means that they adhere to the professional norms and principles appropriate to the scholarly vocation. Which means two things to me: first, that scholars should make an effort to share the knowledge that they are producing with the wider society; and second, that scholars should make an effort to police the boundaries of scholarship and point out where empirical claims that come into the scholar’s area of professional competence are problematic. Putting this more bluntly: communicate, and critique. And that’s it. If one wants to change policy or some other concrete thing in the world, then one shouldn’t be or speak as a scholar, because this would be a violation of the specific vocation of the scholar — which is to produce ideal-typical knowledge through a disciplined application of conceptual instruments derived from specific value-commitments.

Yes, Weber said almost all of this many years ago; I do not claim originality for these insights. I just happen to believe that Weber was right that in the end, “scholarship” and “politics” are names for vocations: modes of living and of comporting oneself with respect to the world. Vocations are in this way more about identity than they are about any sort of specific outcome. Remember that Weber was quite close to Kant in maintaining that ethical action is not about consequences but is about conformity with various abstract principles and procedures — in this case, principles and procedures that constitute a particular identity category. The operative question, then, is: does this course of action conform to the kind of person that I envision myself as being, with the specific vocation in question representing an important facet of that person? Or: “Would a scholar do this?” The trick here is that there is no simple and finite list of characteristics that constitute a “scholar”; instead, there are a set of issues and distinctions that a would-be “scholar” (and in this approach I am sketching here, everyone who thinks of themselves as a scholar is a “would-be scholar” — no one has gotten it completely “right,” because that’s not really possible) has to confront. To have a vocation for scholarship is to accept, at least provisionally, these issues and distinctions as the things that one has to wrestle with — and to keep on wrestling with them.

For my part, thinking through the specific responsibilities of the scholarly vocation led me to conclude that SSSFP was okay as long as we didn’t take any partisan money or make electoral recommendations — or explicitly intervene in the election campaign. I don’t think that we did, so I think we stayed on the scholarly side of the line. And that’s enough for me: SSSFP was a good and appropriate scholarly activity, regardless of the outcome. I wasn’t trying to be effective; I was trying to appropriately fulfill my responsibilities as a scholar. And I think that we did that.

Share

© 2020 Duck of Minerva

Theme by Anders NorenUp ↑